teisipäev, 27. september 2022

VALITSEMISE INSTITUTSIONAALNE KONTEKST: õigeusklik-bütsantslik valitsemiskultuur ja Vene-Ukraina sõda

 SISSEKANNE # 176

Alljärgneva mõttearenduse on PVA õpiku valitsuskultuuride võrdluse tabel, õieti selle laiendus, mis kaasab õigeusklik-bütsantsliku valitsemiskultuuri kui neljanda võimaluse, mille viljelejaks on nt Balkani riigid, Ungari (tendentsid Orbani võimuloleku ajal), endised Nõukogude Liidu slaavi riigid ja kõige ilmsemal kujul Venemaa. Püüan analüüsida Venemaa agressiivse-ekspansiivse sõja põhjusi ja geopoliitilisi mustreid sõja ümber sellest lähtuvalt.

 

PVA, 2011

 

Õigeusklik-bütsantslik valitsemiskultuur on sügavalt hierarhiline ja tugevalt tsentraliseeritud süsteem, kus keskpunktis (või tipus) asub tugev liider,  kes juhib (ideaalis) kindla käega riiki. Kehtib struktuurne võim – vastuoksa distributiivsele -, milles võimu mõistetakse kui süsteemi ja inimest kui üha suurema tegevusruumiga toimijat selles rüsteemis. Max Weberi järgi kaasneb struktuurne võim ametikohaga. Venemaa president Putin on weberliku bürokraatiaaparaadi täiuslik toode: pole vaja karismat ega erakordseid andeid, kuid nn õukondliku intriigi valdamine on hädavajalik. Ametikohtade täitmine toimub fraktsioonide tasakaalu tagamiseks ja poliitika kujundatakse vastavalt haldussüsteemi vajadustele. Putini aja  institutsionaalsed uuendused tugevdasid näiliselt valgustatud valitsemise tehnokraatlikku ratsionaalsust ja seetõttu kohtasid nad nii vähe olemasoleva eliidi vastupanu (Sakwa, 2020).

Poliitika on seega pigem võimuvõitlus juhile lähemale pääsemiseks, pigem õukonnaintriigid kui konkurents maailmavaateliste programmide realiseerimiseks. Juht saavutab oma liidrirolli neid surveid tasakaalustades (PVA, 2011). Seepärast on mõistetavad ka tugevalt isikustatud võimusuhted selle valitsemiskultuuri raames. Iseloomulik on autoriteedi kultus, inimese alamlik positsioon kõrgema võimu suhtes, millega suhestutakse läbi hirmu, austuse ja leppimuse, kuid paradoksaalselt madalamatesse võimustruktuuridesse, mida esindavad nt kohalikud ametnikud, suhtutakse põlguse ja ükskõiksusega (siloviki vs tśinovniki). Siin saab rääkida ka pika ajalooga sotsiaalpoliitilisest diskursusest „hea tsaar ja tema kurjad bojaarid“.

Venemaa on presidentaalne, tsentraliseeritud ja etatistlik riik.  Valitseb nõrk mitmeparteiline poliitiline süsteem, kus on kahekojaline seadusandlik kogu (Fõderaalassamblee), mis jaguneb alamkojaks (Riigiduuma) ja ülemkojaks (Föderatsiooninõukogu). D Kelley (2016) leiab, et Vene presidentaalset riiki ei saa mõista täidesaatva võimu ajaloolis-kultuurilise tausta uurimiseta, kuna see on mõjutatud paljudest teguritest alates tsaarivõimust läbi kommunistliku reźiimi kuni 21. sajandi autokraatiani välja. D. Giles (2018) sedastab, et autoritaarsus on Venemaa valitsemiskultuuri norm, elementaarne vajadus, eeltingimus toimivaks valitsemiseks. Autoritaarsust põhjendatakse nii geopoliitiliste oludega – hoomamatu suurusega, eri kultuuri- ja ajavööndeid hõlmav riik -  kui geneetilise soodumusega (arhailine talupojarahvas, kes tegelikult ei vaja riiki, vaid ainult tugevat tsaari). Siin võiks parafraseerida välisminister Lavrovi, kelle sõnul on „venelased kindlasti konservatiivid, ainult et me peame enne aru saama, mida see sõna täpselt tähendab.“ (Giles, 2018).

D. Lewise järgi  (cit. Giles, 2018) on Venemaa poliitilise süsteemi raamid üldjoones järgmised: esiteks, hobbesiaanlik poliitiline kord, kus tugev riik ja hierarhiline poliiteliit on käsitletavad kui kaitsevall kaose vastu, kõik toimijad alluvad reźiimile; teiseks, sügav kahtlus lääne mõjude suhtes koos pideva rahvusvahelise austuse, staatuse ja aktsepteerimise otsimisega; kolmandaks, machiavellilik nägemus rahvast  kui "tänamatust, heitlikust, valelikust, argpükslikust, ahnest“ massist“,  kes on altid lääne luureagentuuride või hoolimatute opositsioonijuhtide manipuleerimisele; neljandaks, pühendumine majanduskasvu ja struktuurireformi mantratele ning täielikule lõimumisele globaalsesse finantseliiti, pärssides samas tõelist turumajanduslikku arengut.  Viimasel juhul näeme näiteks Venemaa lakkamatut pürgimist suurte majandusklubide sekka (G8, G20).

Siit edasi tuleb vaadelda Venemaa ideoloogilisi raame. Miks? Need selgitavad olukorda, kus me oleme täna, septembris 2022.  Venemaal on läbi ajaloo olnud läänlaste ja slavofiilide diskussioon, millele 21. sajandil on lisandunud nn eurasianism, kus Venemaad vaadeldakse kui Aasia ja Euroopa hiigelsulamit.

Großraumi teooria (Carl Schmitt) ja selle eurasianistlik modifikatsioon Aleksander Duginilt pakub raamistiku, milles Venemaa vastandub domineerivale rahvusvahelisele liberaalsele korrale. Großraumi mõtteviisid viitavad neljale peamisele väitele Venemaa välispoliitika kohta: 1) Venemaad ei saa piirata kaasaegse rahvusriigi piiridega, vaid ta saab oma identiteeti kinnitada vaid suurema ruumi liigendamise kaudu, mis ei lange kokku tema formaalsete riigipiiridega; 2) Venemaa toimib selles ruumis „poliitiliselt ärganud“ rahvana, kelle suveräänsus on tagatud, kuid kelle mõju ulatub ruumi, mille on hõivanud teised riigid, kes seetõttu naudivad vaid osalist suveräänsust; 3) Venemaa on selles ruumis „poliitilise idee” kandja, väärtuste ja ideede kogum, mis ühendab rahvaid kogu regioonis rahvust ületavatel viisidel; 4) Venemaa domineeritud Großraum püüab välistada võõrvõimude ideoloogilist, poliitilist ja sõjalist kohalolekut (Giles, 2018)

Siit tuletub loogiliselt Vene maailma (Russki mir) kontseptsioon koos geopoliitilise üksindusega, mille kohaselt Venemaa oma dualistliku riikluse[1], hübriidmentaliteedi, mandriülese territooriumi ja bipolaarse ajalooga saab olla vaid iseenda liitlane (Surkov, 2018). Sellele sekundeerib idee Venemaast kui saarest (Tsõmburski, 2007).

Lõpuks võib välja tuua katehhontilise mõtteviisi, mille kandjaks on eeskätt Vene õigeusu kirik: Venemaa kui kaasaja katehhon. Selle sügavalt tunnetusliku ja hämara mõiste taga on idee Kolmanda Rooma taastamises selle ajalooliselt õiglastes (mõju)piirides, mis ühtlasi tähendab kaasmaalaste hõlmamist nn kaotatud aladel. Kõige kõrgemal võimutasandil on normiks kuulutatud kannatus selle eshatoloogilises mõttes – nagu Nikolai Berdjajev tõdes, et venelased on enim kannatav rahvas, peale juutide (Lewis, 2020).

Kui arvesse võtta kõiki eelpool mainitud asjaolusid, siis asetub Venemaa agressioon Ukraina suhtes, mis algas 2014 ja eskaleerus veebruaris 2022, loogilisse konteksti.  Putini kaks kõnet 21.02.2022  ja 24.02.2022  illusteerivad õpetlike tüvitekstidena õigeusklik-bütsantslikku konstrueeritud loogikat. Kus sobivat ajalugu ei eksisteeri, siis mõeldakse see välja. Müüdid ja pooltõed rakendatakse reźiimi teenistusse, kus need täidavad legitimiseerivat rolli. Venemaal on tõe kohta kaks mõistet - pravda ja istina -, milles esimene on taktikaline ja teine tegelik tõde. Pravda võib olla kooskõlas eetiliste, moraalsete või juriidiliste korrektsuse standarditega. Kuid istina viitab metafüüsilistele, muutumatutele tõdedele elu, olemasolu ja universumi kohta. See eksisteerib sõltumatult maistest arusaamadest, nagu õiglus, eetika ja moraal, ning seda võib pidada kõrgemaks. Võib esineda pravda astmeid, näiteks polupravda (pooltõde) või nepravda (ebatõde). Selle üle, mis on pravda, võib arutleda. Kuid istina astmeid ei saa kvantifitseerida (Giles).

 

 

Allikad:

 

·         Poliitika ja valitsemise alused (2011). Toimetajate kolleegium. Tallinna Ülikool: riigiteaduste instituut.

·         Giles, K. (2018) Moscow Rules. [edition unavailable]. Brookings Institution Press. Available at: https://www.perlego.com/book/742362/moscow-rules-pdf

·         Kelley, D. (2016). Russian Politics and Presidential Power (1st ed.). SAGE Publications. https://www.perlego.com/book/2800774/russian-politics-and-presidential-power-pdf

·         Lewis, D. (2020). Russia’s New Authoritarianism : Putin and the Politics of Order ([edition unavailable]). Edinburgh University Press. https://www.perlego.com/book/2326969/russias-new-authoritarianism-putin-and-the-politics-of-order-pdf

·         Sakwa, R. (2020). The Putin Paradox (1st ed.). Bloomsbury Publishing. https://www.perlego.com/book/1378309/the-putin-paradox-pdf



[1] Vrd Ernst Fraenkeli dualistlik riik: natsireźiim koosnes kahest sfäärist: normatiivne – legaal-administratiivne bürokraatia valitses kehtivate seaduste raames, prerogatiivne – NSDAP+Gestapo tegutsesid väljaspool seadust, kõrgemate eesmärkide nimel, ja kontrollisid/võimustasid normatiivset sfääri.

teisipäev, 20. september 2022

Mark Bevir & R.A.W. Rhodes. STATE AS A CULTURAL PRACTICE. Ch 5. Rethinking the State

 ENTRY # 175


In this chapter, we offer our theory of the stateless state, building on the anti-foundational philosophy and the interpretive theory. We do not provide a historical survey of the extensive and varied literature on social science theories of the state (...)  Rather, we focus on recent developments in the literature analysing the state; namely the various claims that there has been a change in the pattern and exercise of state authority from government to network governance; from a hierarchic or bureaucratic state to governance in and by networks. We identify three waves in this literature discussing the changing state; from government to network governance, metagovernance and bringing the state back in again, and decentred governance and its anti-foundational move to the stateless state.

The literature on governance focuses on the institutional legacy of neoliberal reforms of the state. Governance is associated with the changing nature of the state following the public sector reforms of the 1980s. The reforms are said to have precipitated a shift from a hierarchic bureaucracy toward a greater use of markets, quasi-markets, and networks, especially in the delivery of public services. The effects of the reforms were intensified by global changes, including an increase in transnational economic dows and the rise of regional institutions such as the European Union. The resulting complexity and fragmentation are such that the state increasingly depends on other organizafions to secure its intentions and deliver its policies. Governance evokes a world in which state power is dispersed among a vast array of spatially and functionally distinct networks made up of many public, voluntary, and private organizations with which the centre now interacts. The governance literature offers a compelling picture of the state; indeed Marsh (2008b, 738) is concerned it ‘may be becoming the new orthodoxy’ (see also Kerr and Kettell 2006, 13). We will decentre this hrst-wave approach to network governance, examining the work of the Anglo-governance school.

The second wave of metagovemance accepted the shift from bureaucracy to markets to networks but disputed it led to any significant dispersal of state authority. It focused on metagovemance or ‘the governance of government and governance’ (Jessop 2000, 23; 2007fi). Metagovernance is an umbrella concept that describes the role of the state and its characteristic policy instruments in network governance. Given that governing is distributed among various private, voluntary, and public actors, and that power and authority are more decentralized and fragmented among a plurality of networks, the role of the state has shifted from the direct governance of society to the ’metagovernance’ of the several modes of intervention and from command and control through bureaucracy to the indirect steering of relatively autonomous stakeholders. We also decentre this attempt at bringing the state back in (yet again) ( Jessop 2007a, 54).

Third, we argue for a third-wave narrative of ‘decentred governance’ that challenges the idea there are inexorable, impersonal forces driving a shift from government to network governance. As we have seen, to decentre is to focus on the social construction of a practice through the ability of individuals to create, and act on, meanings. Thus, we argue that governance is constructed differently by many actors working against the background of diverse traditions. In effect, we pronounce the death of the Anglo-governance school, of metagovernance, and of the state. We argue, in their place, for the analysis of the various traditions that have informed the diverse policies and practices by which elite and other actors have sought to remake the state.

Finally, we explore the implication of this shift to a narrative of decentred governance. We challenge a craving for generality that characterizes the earlier waves of network and metagovernance and define governance as a series of family resemblances, none of which need be always present. There is no list of general features or essential properties that are supposed to characterize governance in every instance. Rather, there are diverse practices composed of multiple individuals acting on changing webs of beliefs rooted in overlapping traditions. Patterns of governance or state authority arise as the contingent products of diverse actions and political struggles informed by the beliefs of agents as they arise against a backcloth of traditions. We discuss the new research topics prompted by this conception of the stateless state.

 

The first wave of governance: the Anglo-governance school

 

Social scientists typically describe network governance as consisting of something akin to a differentiated polity characterized by a hollowed-out state, a core executive fumbling to pull rubber levers of control, and, most notably, a massive growth of networks. Of course, people define governance in all kinds of ways. Nonetheless, social scientists typically appeal to inexorable, impersonal forces, to logics of modernization, such as the functional differentiation of the modern state or the marketization of the public sector, to explain the shift from hierarchy to network governance by markets and especially networks. Indeed, neoliberal reforms did not lead to markets but to the further differentiation of policy networks in an increasingly hollow state. Social scientists typically use a concept of differentiation here to evoke specialization based on function. They offer a modernist-empiricist account of network governance. They treat governance as self-organizing, inter-organizational networks;  as a complex set of institutions and institutional linkages defined by their social role or function. They make any appeal to the contingent beliefs and preferences of agents largely irrelevant.

 

The Anglo-governance school

In Britain, the first wave of governance narratives challenges the longstanding Westminster narrative, claiming to capture recent changes in British government in a way the Westminster narrative did not. They start with the notion of policy networks or sets of organizations clustered around a major government function or department. These organizations commonly include the professions, trade unions, and big business. So, the story continues, central departments need the cooperation of such groups to deliver services. They allegedly need their cooperation because British government rarely delivers services itself; it uses other bodies to do so. Also, there are supposed to be too many groups to consult so government must aggregate interests; it needs the legitimated spokespeople for that policy area. The groups in turn need the money and legislative authority that only government can provide.

 

Policy networks are a long-standing feature of British government; they are its silos or velvet drainpipes. The Conservative government of Margaret Thatcher sought to reduce their power by using markets to deliver public services, bypassing existing networks and curtailing the ‘privileges’ of professions, commonly by subjecting them to the rigorous financial and management controls of the new public management.

The new public management, or managerialism, is conventionally seen as a prime example of governmental control technologies or rationalities. The term encompasses managerialism and marketization. Managerialism refers to introducing private sector management methods to the public sector. It stresses hands-on professional management, explicit standards, and measures of performance; managing by results; value for money; and, more recently, closeness to the customer. Marketization refers to introducing incentive structures (such as market competition) into public service provision. It stresses disaggregating bureaucracies; greater competition through contracting-out and quasi-markets; and consumer choice. But these reforms had unintended consequences. They fragmented the systems for delivering public services, creating pressures for organizations to cooperate with one another to deliver services. In other words, marketization multiplied the networks it aimed to replace. Commonly, packages of organizations now deliver welfare state services. First-wave governance narratives thus concentrate on the spread of networks in British government. They tell us not only that fragmentation created new networks but it also increased the membership of existing networks, incorporating both the private and voluntary sectors. They also tell us that the government swapped direct for indirect controls so central departments are no longer either necessarily or invariably the fulcrum of a network. The government can set the limits to network actions: after all, it still funds the services. But it has also increased its dependence on multifarious networks.

The Anglo-governance school conceives of networks as a distinctive coordinating mechanism notably different from markets and hierarchies and not a hybrid of them. They associate networks with characteristics such as interdependence and trust. In their view, trust is essential because it is the basis of network coordination in the same way that commands and price competition are the key mechanisms for bureaucracies and markets respectively (see also Frances et al. 1991, 15; Powell 1991). Shared values and norms are the glue that holds the complex set of relationships in a network together. Trust and reciprocity are essential for cooperative behaviour and, therefore, the existence of the network (see, e.g. Kramer and Tyler 1996). With the spread of networks there has been a recurrent tension betweencontracts on the one hand, with their stress on competition to get the best price, and networks on the other, with their stress on cooperative behaviour.

According to the Anglo-governance school, multiplying networks means that core executive coordination is modest in practice. It is largely negative, based on persistent compartmentalization, mutual avoidance, and friction reduction between powerful bureaux or ministries. Even when cooperative, anchored at the lower levels of the state machine and organized by specific established networks, coordination is sustained by a culture of dialogue in vertical relations and by horizontal integration. In this view, coordination is rarely strategic, so almost all attempts to create proactive strategic capacity for long-term planning have failed (Wright and Hayward 2000). The Anglo-governance school explains New Labour’s reforms as an attempt to promote coordination and strategic oversight and combat both Whitehall’s departmentalism and the unintended consequences of managerialism.

Therefore, the Anglo-governance school tells us a story of fragmentation confounding centralization as a segmented executive seeks to improve horizontal coordination among departments and agencies and vertical coordination between departments and their networks of organizations. An unintended consequence of this search for central control has been a hollowing out of the state. The hollowing out of the state suggests the growth of governance has further undermined the ability of the core executive to act effectively, making it increasingly reliant on diplomacy. The state has been hollowed out from above by for example international interdependence, and from below by for example marketization and networks, and sideways by agencies. Internally, the British core executive was already characterized by baronies, policy networks, and intermittent and selective coordination. It has been further hollowed out internally by the unintended consequences of marketization, which fragmented service delivery, multiplied networks, and diversified the membership of those networks. Externally, the state is also being hollowed out by membership of the EU and other international commitments.

 

The second wave: metagovernance

 

Critics of the first wave characteristically focus on the argument the state has been hollowed out. For example, Pierre and Peters (2000, 78, 104–5, and 111) argue that the shift to network governance could ‘increase public control over society’ because governments ‘rethink the mix of policy instruments’. As a result ‘coercive or regulatory instruments become less important and ... “softer” instruments gain importance’, for example, steering through brokerage. In short, the state has not been hollowed out but reasserted its capacity to govern by regulating the mix of governing structures such as markets and networks and using indirect instruments of control.

Metagovernance refers to this role of the state in securing coordination in governance and its use of negotiation, diplomacy, and more informal modes of steering. It suggests the state now steers and regulates sets of organizations, governments, and networks rather than rowing by directly providing services through state bureaucracies. These other organizations undertake much of the work of governing: they implement policies, provide public services, and at times even regulate themselves. The state governs the organizations that govern civil society: the governance of governance. Moreover, the other organizations characteristically have a degree of autonomy from the state: they are often voluntary or private sector groups or they are governmental agencies or tiers of government separate from the core executive. So the state cannot govern them solely by the instruments that work in bureaucracies.

Nonetheless, there are several ways in which the state can steer the other actors involved in governance (see, e.g. Jessop 2000, 23–4; 2007b). First, the state can set the rules of the game for other actors and then leave them to do what they will within those rules; they work ‘in the shadow of hierarchy’. So, it can redesign markets, re-regulate policy sectors, or introduce consti- tutional change. Second, the state can try to steer other actors using storytelling. It can organize dialogues; foster meanings, beliefs, and identities among the relevant actors; and influence what actors think and do. Third, the state can steer by the way in which it distributes resources such as money and authority. It can play a boundary-spanning role; alter the balance between actors in a network; act as a court of appeal when conflict arises; rebalance the mix of governing structures; and step in when network governance fails. Of course, the state need not adopt a single uniform approach to metagovernance. It can use different approaches, in different settings, at different times.

This summary implies much agreement about metagovernance. In fact, Sørensen and Torfing (2007, 170–80) identify four approaches to meta- governance: interdependence, governability, integration, and governmen- tality. Interdependence theory focuses on the state managing networks using a more sophisticated, indirect tool kit (Rhodes 1997b). Governability theory stresses that metagovernance and network management occur in the shadow of hierarchy (Scharpf 1997). Integration theory stresses the formation and management of identities (March and Olsen 1989). Govern- mentality theory focuses on the regulation of self-regulation: on the norms, standards, and targets that set the limits to networks (Barry, Osborne, and Rose 1996a). This categorization is odd. Proponents of integration theory and governmentality never talk of metagovernance, although some of their ideas are relevant, while integration theory lumps together strange bedfellows. Nonetheless, distinguishing these approaches helps to identify the differences over the extent and form of state intervention and control. Proponents of interdependence theory would argue that manipulating the rules of the game allows the state to keep much control over governing without having to bear the costs of direct interference. Proponents of governability theory stress the resources the state has at its disposal for metagovernance. They argue that the state can easily deploy these resources to manage other policy actors. Proponents of integration theory argue the viewpoints and interests of different actors are so diverse that managing identities is the core task; for example – storytelling about best practice and successful cooperation and coordination. Storytelling can create coherent social and political meanings and identities that soften the tensions among competing viewpoints and interests. Proponents of governmentality theory identify the complex of rules, norms, standards, and regulatory practices that extend state rule more deeply into civil society by regulating the ways in which civil society self-regulates. Accountancy, performance management, and other management techniques are not just ways of achieving the ‘3Es’ of economy, efficiency, and effectiveness. They are also ways of measuring, approving, appraising, and regulating the beliefs and practices of network actors (and for examples see McKinlay and Starkey 1998). Of course, the approaches are not mutually exclusive; state actors use a different mix of approaches in different contexts.

 

Common ground

 

For all their different emphases and the debate between the several proponents, the first two waves of governance share much common ground. First, proponents of metagovernance take for granted the characteristics of network governance. They accept that states are becoming increasingly fragmented into networks based on several different stakeholders; and the dividing line between the state and civil society is becoming more blurred because the relevant stakeholders are private or voluntary sector organizations. So, Jessop (2000, 24) concedes ‘the state is no longer the sovereign authority ... [it is] less hierarchical, less centralised, less dirigiste’. There is a shared modernist-empiricist description of the characteristics of network governance.

Second, the analysis of metagovernance not only recognizes non-state actors by granting them the power to self-regulate but also distinguishes them from the state so creating the space for the state to exert macro- control over their self-regulation. The state governs the other actors involved in governance. In other words, metagovernance heralds the re- turn of the state by reinventing its governing role. This return to the state opens opportunities for policy advice on the practice of metagovernance. The two waves share a common concern with providing advice on network governance. Both assume the role of the state is to manage, directly and indirectly, the networks of service delivery. For example, Part III of Sørensen and Torfing (2007, chapters 10–12) on ‘metagovernance’ is devoted to such topics as governing the performance of networks, institutional design, and network management, and the possibilities for public authorities to shape network outputs. They are not alone.

Third, both narratives rely on a reified notion of structure. The proponents of first-wave governance are self-confessed modernist-empiricists with a reified notion of structure rooted in an explicit social science theory of functional differentiation. The proponents of metagovernance also claim the state is a material object, a structure, or a social form. They draw on critical realist epistemology and such notions as ‘emergence’ and ‘mechanisms’ ostensibly to guard against the charge of reification (see, e.g. Jessop 2005, 2007a). Their position is flawed and has a closer affinity to modernist-empiricism than they realize or care to admit.

Modernist-empiricists rely on reified concepts such as institution, structure, state formation, and system to offer explanations that transcend time and space. They appeal to ideal types, institutions, and structures as if they are natural kinds. Rational choice theory challenges the reifications and raises the issue of micro-theory. Modernist-empiricists can respond in three ways. First, they could adopt the third-wave decentred approach. They could view social life solely as activity, reject reifications, and avoid rational choice theory by emphasizing contingency. They don’t like this route because they have to give up their ideas about expertise, science, and some varieties of socialism (and often all three). Second, they can recast their reifications as if they were consequences of rational actors behaving more or less as rational choice theory suggests. This response is common in the United States but not with critical realists in the United Kingdom. They prefer to appeal to structure, emergence, and mechanism. They claim these concepts do not involve reification but they avoid the micro-level questions that would show how they avoid reification. Thus, they often shift back and forth between using the old reifications of modernist-empiricism and paying lip service to the micro-theories associated with rational choice or decentred analysis. For example, McAnulla (2006) argues that structures are emergent or temporal mechanisms rather than reifications, but never explains how these structures differ from practices, or how they determine individual actions without passing through intentional consciousness. He provides no clear account of why agents can’t change emergent structures. The structure emerges from actions, so presumably, if all the relevant people change their actions, they will stop producing that structure, so changing it. The emergent structures are better understood as practices. They consist simply of what a bundle of people do and the unintended consequences of these actions. Of course, structure can be used as a meta- phor for the way activity coalesces into patterns and practices. But the metaphors have a bewitching effect. People treat them as real, reified entities; the fate of Marsh (2008a) in his analysis of the British political tradition. In short, critical realism and the analysis of metagovernance all too often rely on the reifications of modernist-empiricism and of first- wave governance.

The idea of the state as a structure is useful only if we unpack it into the specific notions of tradition, dilemma, practice, and unintended consequence. First, the state might refer to traditions; that is, inherited webs of belief that influence what people do. Second, the state might refer to a subset of dilemmas; that is, to intersubjective views about the way the nature of the world precludes or impels certain actions. Third, the state might refer to cultural practices, where although these practices arise from people’s actions, they then confront other people as if objective social facts. Finally, the state might refer to the intended and unintended consequences of meaningful actions, although, of course, to explain such consequences, we would have to refer to the actions and the meanings (or intentionality) they embodied.

Finally, both waves seek to provide comprehensive accounts of network and metagovernance. Social scientists typically aim to provide a general account of what governance looks like, and why it does so. For example, network governance is often characterized by the shift from bureaucratic hierarchies to multiplying networks. This defining feature is then said to explain other characteristics of network governance such as the need for indirect ‘diplomatic’ styles of management, and the search for better coor- dination through joint ventures, partnerships, and holistic governance.

Defining network and metagovernance by one or more essential properties, such as multiplying networks, implies these properties are general and characterize all cases of governance. So, we will find governance in its new guise if and only if we find a spread of networks. Moreover, these essential properties explain the most significant features of network and metagovernance.

A comprehensive account of governance makes sense, even as a mere aspiration, only if it has some essence. We should seek a comprehensive account only if the way to define and explain network and metagovernance is to find a social logic or essential property that is at least common to all its manifestations and ideally even explains them. But why would we assume that network and metagovernance has one or more essential feature?

The search for comprehensive accounts arises from a preoccupation with the natural sciences. However, even if appropriate in the natural sciences, it is counterproductive in the human sciences. Human practices are not governed by social logics or law-like regularities associated with their allegedly essential properties. They arise instead out of the contingent activity of individuals. Therefore, when we seek to explain particular cases of governance, we should do so by reference to the contingent activity of the relevant individuals, not to a social logic or law-like regularity. We should explain practices, including cases of governance, using narratives that unpack the contingent actions that embody beliefs informed by contested traditions and dilemmas. The contingent nature of the links between traditions and their development undermines the possibility of a comprehensive account that could relate any one practice to a specific set of social conditions as opposed to a historical process. If we explore these possibilities, we will adopt a decentred approach that refutes the narratives of previous waves.

 

 

The third wave: decentring the changing state

 

Decentred theory

Decentred theory explores the institutions of the state as the contingent meanings that inform the actions of the individuals involved in all kinds of practices of rule. It is a humanist and historicist theory of the state. It refuses to treat the state as uniform. The state contains diverse practices. In rejecting uniform concepts of the state, we echo those pluralists and behaviouralists who developed the twentieth-century critique of the state. The state has no defined or metaphysical nature fixed by the common good of its people or any other essence. It needs, instead, to be differentiated into its constituents.

First-wave narratives of the changing state focus on issues such as the objective characteristics of policy networks and the oligopoly of the political market place. They stress power dependency, the relationship of the size of networks to policy outcomes, and the strategies by which the centre might steer networks.

The second wave of narratives about the changing state focus on the mix of governing structures such as markets and net- works and using various instruments of control such as changing the rules of the game, storytelling, and changing the distribution of resources.

In contrast to these comprehensive, reified views of governance, a third- wave decentred narrative focuses on the social construction of patterns of rule through the ability of individuals to create meanings in action. It encourages us to examine the ways in which patterns of rule, including institutions and policies, are created, sustained, and varied by individuals. It encourages us to recognize that the actions of these individuals are not fixed by institutional norms or a social logic of modernization. To the contrary, actions arise from the beliefs individuals adopt against the back- ground of traditions and in response to dilemmas.

Any existing pattern of rule will have some failings. Different people will have different views about these failings since they are not simply given by experience but rather constructed from interpretations of experience infused with traditions. When people’s perceptions of the failings of governance conflict with their existing beliefs, the resulting dilemmas lead them to reconsider beliefs and traditions. Because people confront these dilemmas against the background of diverse traditions, there arises a political contest over what constitutes the nature of the failings and what should be done about them. This contest leads to a reform of governance. The reformed pattern of rule poses new dilemmas, leading to a further contest over meanings and policy agendas. All these contests are governed by laws and norms that prescribe how they should be conducted. Some- times the relevant laws and norms have changed because of simultaneous contests over their content and relevance. Yet while we can distinguish analytically between a pattern of rule and a contest over its reform, we rarely can do so temporally. Rather, the activity of governing continues during most contests, and most contests occur partially in local practices of governing. What we have, therefore, is a complex and continuous process of interpretation, conflict, and activity that produces ever-changing patterns of rule.

A decentred account of the changing state represents, therefore, a shift from institutions to meanings in action, and from social logics to narratives. The first-wave narrative of network governance reduces the diversity of governance to a social logic of modernization, institutional norms, or a set of classifications or correlations across networks. Its proponents tame an otherwise chaotic picture of multiple actors creating a contingent pat- tern of rule through their diverse understandings and conflicting actions. The second-wave of governance compounds this mistake by reinventing the state’s capacity to control. The third-wave narrative decentres the changing state into governance practices. Thus, governance arises from the bottom-up because it arises from diverse practices, conflicting mean- ings and beliefs, competing traditions, and varied dilemmas. The third-wave narrative replaces aggregate concepts that refer to objectified social laws with ones that explain actions by relating them to the beliefs and desires that produce them.

What does this decentred approach tell us about governance? We have two answers. First, we offer a definition of governance as a series of family resemblances that does not crave generality and aspire to comprehensiveness because none of the resemblances need be always present. Second, we point to some of the distinctive research topics that spring from a decentred approach. Our concern with diverse and contingent meanings encourages a focus on such new empirical topics as rule, rationalities, and resistance.

 

Defining governance

A decentred approach to the changing state contrasts sharply with comprehensive accounts that seek to unpack the essential properties and social logic of network governance and metagovernance. Neither the intrinsic rationality of markets nor the path dependency of institutions decide patterns of governance. Rather, patterns of governance are explained as the contingent constructions of several actors inspired by competing webs of belief and associated traditions. A decentred approach explains shifting patterns of governance by focusing on the actors’ own interpretations of their actions and practices. It explores the diverse ways in which situated agents are changing the boundaries of state and civil society by constantly remaking practices as their beliefs change. Because we cannot explain cases of network and metagovernance by reference to a comprehensive theory, we cannot define governance by its key features. Rather, we can define it only for particular cases. However, the absence of a comprehensive theory of governance also implies that there need be no feature common to all the cases to which we would apply the term. It is futile to search for the essential features of an abstract category that denotes a cluster of human practices. Worse still, the search for allegedly common features can lead political scientists to dismiss the particular cases which are essential to understanding the abstract category. When we provide a definition or general account of governance, it should be couched as a set of family resemblances.

Wittgenstein (1972a) famously suggested that general concepts such as ‘game’ should be defined by various traits that overlapped and criss-crossed in much the same way as do the resemblances between members of a family – their builds, eye colour, gait, or personalities. He considered various examples of games to challenge the idea that they all possessed a given property or set of properties – skill, enjoyment, victory, and defeat – by which we could define the concept. Instead, he suggested the examples exhibited a network of similarities, at various levels of detail, so they coalesced even though no one feature was common to them all.

We do not master such family resemblance concepts by discovering a theory or rule that tells us precisely when we should and should not apply them. Our grasp of the concept consists in our ability to explain why it should be applied in one case but not another, our ability to draw analogies with other cases, and our ability to point to the criss-crossing similarities. Our knowledge of ‘governance’ is analogous to our knowledge of ‘game’ as described by Wittgenstein. It is ‘completely expressed’ by our describing various cases of governance, showing how other cases can be considered as analogous to these, and suggesting that we would be unlikely to describe yet other cases as ones of governance.

Some of the family resemblances that characterize governance derive from a focus on meaning in action and so apply to all patterns of rule. A decentred approach highlights, first, a more diverse view of state authority and its exercise. All patterns of rule arise as the contingent products of diverse actions and political struggles informed by the varied beliefs of situated agents. First-wave narratives of network governance suggest the New Right’s reinvention of the minimal state and the more recent rediscovery of networks are attempts to find a substitute for the voluntaristic bonds weakened by state intervention (Harris 1990).

A decentred approach suggests that the notion of a monolithic state in control of itself and civil society was always a myth. The myth obscured the reality of diverse state practices that escaped the control of the centre because they arose from the contin- gent beliefs and actions of diverse actors at the boundary of state and civil society. The state is never monolithic and it always negotiates with others.

Policy always arises from interactions within networks of organizations and individuals. Patterns of rule always traverse the public, private, and voluntary sectors. The boundaries between state and civil society are always blurred. Transnational and international links and flows always disrupt national borders. In short, state authority is constantly remade, negotiated, and contested in widely different ways within widely varying everyday practices.

A decentred approach suggests, second, these everyday practices arise from situated agents whose beliefs and actions are informed by traditions and expressed in stories. In every government department, we can identify departmental traditions, often embodied in rituals and routines. They might range from specific notions of accountability to the ritual of the tea lady. Actors pass on these traditions in large part by telling one another stories about ‘how we do things around here’, and about what does and does not work. For example, British civil servants are socialized into the broad notions of the Westminster tradition, such as ministerial responsibility, as well as the specific ways of doing things around here. They are ‘socialized into the idea of a profession’, and learn ‘the framework of the acceptable’ (Bevir and Rhodes 2006). Governance is not any given set of characteristics. It is the stories people use to construct, convey, and explain traditions, dilemmas, beliefs, and practices.

A decentred approach also might help to highlight a third family resemblance that characterizes British governance, but might not be found in patterns of rule in other times or places. In Britain, the reforms of the New Right and New Labour have brought about a shift from hierarchy to markets to networks. While this shift is widely recognized, a decentred approach suggests, crucially, that it takes many diverse forms. For the police, the shift from hierarchy to markets to networks poses specific dilemmas. They know how to rewrite the rulebook, manage a contract, or work with neighbourhood watch, but they struggle to reconcile these ways of working, believing they conflict and undermine one another (Bevir and Rhodes 2006). For doctors, the equivalent shift poses different dilemmas: the key issue is how to preserve the medical model of health and medical autonomy from managerial reforms that stress hierarchy and financial control (Bevir and Rhodes 2006).

A fourth family resemblance is that the central state has adopted a less hands-on role. Its actors are less commonly found within various local and sectoral bodies, and more commonly found in quangos concerned to steer, coordinate, and regulate such bodies. Once again, a decentred approach suggests, crucially, that such steering, coordination, and regulation take many diverse forms. In Britain, the pre-eminent recent example is ‘joined-up’ government as the Blair government sought to devise policy instruments that integrated both horizontally across central government departments and vertically between central and local government and the voluntary sector (Bevir 2005, 83–105).

A decentred approach highlights the resemblances that contribute to a general characterization of governance and a more specific characterization of governance at least in Britain. Nonetheless, it disavows any logic to the specific forms that governance takes in particular circumstances. So, a decentred approach resolves the theoretical difficulties that beset earlier waves or narratives of the changing state. It avoids the unacceptable suggestion that institutions fix the actions of individuals in them rather than being products of those actions. It replaces unhelpful phrases such as path dependency with an analysis of change rooted in the beliefs and practices of situated agents. Yet it allows political scientists to offer aggregate studies by using the concept of tradition to explain how people come to hold certain beliefs and perform certain actions.

 

New research topics

 

A decentred approach to the state rejects both comprehensive theory and the related idea that the state is a material object or emergent structure or social form. We reject the claim that the ‘preexistence [of social forms] implies their autonomy as possible objects of scientific investigation; and their causal efficacy confirms their reality’ (Jessop 2005, 42). We offer a stateless theory in the sense that we reject the idea of the state as a pre- existing causal structure that can be understood independently of people’s beliefs and practices. Studying the changing state is not about building formal theories; it is about telling stories about other people’s meanings; it is about narratives of their narratives. As Finlayson and Martin (2006, 167) stress, the object of analysis is not the state but ‘a diverse range of agencies, apparatuses and practices producing varied mechanisms of control and varied forms of knowledge that make areas or aspects of social life available for governmental action’. A decentred approach leads us to new narratives of such practices and knowledge, which we explore as rule, rationalities, and resistance.

 

RULE – ELITE NARRATIVES

Decentred theory suggests that political scientists should pay more attention to the traditions against the background of which elites construct their worldviews, including their views of their own interests. Moreover, the central elite need not be a uniform group, all the members of which see their interests in the same way, share a common culture, or speak a shared discourse. Our decentred approach suggests that political scientists should ask whether different sections of the elite draw on different traditions to construct different narratives about the world, their place within it, and their interests and values. In Britain, for example, the different members of the central elite are inspired by Tory, Whig, liberal, and socialist narratives. The dominant narratives in the central civil service used to be the Whig story of the generalist civil servant, spotting snags and muddling through. It has been challenged by a liberal managerial narrative that sees civil servants as hands-on, can-do managers, trained at business schools and not on the job. But the traditions coexist sometimes separately but sometimes bumping into one another to create dilemmas. Thus, civil servants continue to believe in the Westminster notions of ministerial accountability to parliament, a centralizing idea, even as they decentralize decision making in line with managerial notions.

 

RATIONALITIES

Central elites may construct their world using diverse narratives but they also turn to forms of expertise for specific discourses. Nowadays different traditions of social science influence public policy. Our decentred approach draws attention to the varied rationalities that inform policies across different sectors and different geographical spaces. Rationalities refer here to the scientific beliefs and associated technologies that govern conduct; it captures the ways in which governments and other social actors draw on knowledge to construct policies and practices, especially those that regulate and create subjectivities. Britain, like much of the developed world, has witnessed the rise of neoliberal managerial rationalities using a technology of performance measurement and targets that spread far beyond the central civil service to encompass the control of localities. Kelly (2006, 615 and 617) describes how the UK’s Audit Commission acts as a meta-governor of local authorities for the New Labour government. It ensures that ‘the regulatory regime is embedded in the everyday operations and actions of local government practitioners’. It espouses the notion of the well-run authority and it works ‘with other inspectorates and professional auditing bodies to maintain professional standards and also to share best practice’. It sets auditors’ fees and standards, and monitors the work of the auditors. It is one of those varied agencies employing indirect mechanisms of control and knowledge.

 

RESISTANCE

When political scientists neglect agency, they can give the impression that politics and policies arise exclusively from the strategies and interactions of central and local elites. Yet other actors can resist, transform, and thwart the agendas of elites. Our decentred approach draws attention to the diverse traditions and narratives that inspire street-level bureaucrats and citizens. Policies are sites of struggles not just between strategic elites, but between all kinds of actors with different views and ideals reached against the background of different traditions. Subordinate actors can resist the intentions and policies of elites by consuming them in ways that draw on their local traditions and their local reasoning. For example, street- level police officers are often influenced by organizational traditions that encourage them to set priorities different from those of both their superior officers and elite policy makers. Combating crime is seen as the core of police work, not the ‘touchy-feely’ areas of community policing. The new police commissioner may want to set an example, cause a stir, or otherwise ginger up the troops. But the troops know he or she will be gone in a few years. There will be a new commissioner with new interests and priorities (see, e.g. on community policing, Fleming and Wood 2006; and on other street-level bureaucrats see Lipsky 1979 and Vinzant and Crothers 1998).

 

 

Conclusions

 

In sum, network governance was the modernist-empiricist story of the changing state that described the shift from hierarchy to markets to networks. A decentred approach brings about the death of this first-wave narrative because, we argue, there is no single account or theory of governance, only the differing constructions of several traditions. We also announce the death of the second wave of metagovernance not only because it accepts the modernist-empiricist narrative but also because it argues for a top-down account of state regulation and control over a bottom-up one. There is no necessary logical or structural process determining the form of network governance or the role of the ‘central state’ in the governance of governance. Patterns of governance, and changes in such patterns, cannot be explained by any of the intrinsic rationality of markets, the path dependency of institutions, or the state’s new tool kit for managing the mix of governing structures.

The third-wave analysis of governance announces the arrival of the stateless state. It argues that the state arises out of the diverse actions and practices inspired by varied beliefs and traditions. The state, or pattern of rule, is the contingent product of diverse actions and political struggles informed by the beliefs of agents rooted in traditions.

Our approach seeks to explain the state by reference to historical meanings infusing the beliefs and practices of individual actors. It encourages political scientists to decentre the state and governance and focus on the social construction of practices. We unpack the state into the disparate and contingent beliefs and actions of individuals. We reveal the contingent and conflicting beliefs that inform the diverse actions that constitute the state. We challenge the idea that inexorable or impersonal forces, norms, or laws define changing patterns of governance. Instead, we argue that the state is constructed differently by many actors inspired by different ideas and values.

(NB! abbr, highlights – R.R.)

*          *          *

Retrieved from:

·         Mark Bevir, Rod Rhodes (2010). The State as Cultural Practice. Oxford, New York: Oxford University Press